Reductionism Vs Holism Essay Contest

On By In 1

Reductionistic and Holistic Science

  1. Ferric C. Fang
  1. Editor in Chief, Infection and Immunity
    Departments of Laboratory Medicine and Microbiology
    University of Washington School of Medicine, Seattle, Washington
  1. Arturo Casadevall
  1. Editor in Chief, mBio
    Departments of Microbiology & Immunology and Medicine
    Albert Einstein College of Medicine, Bronx, New York

ABSTRACT

A reductionistic approach to science, epitomized by molecular biology, is often contrasted with the holistic approach of systems biology. However, molecular biology and systems biology are actually interdependent and complementary ways in which to study and make sense of complex phenomena.

“Reductionism is one of those things, like sin, that is only mentioned by people who are against it.”

—Richard Dawkins (14)

Few scientists will voluntarily characterize their work as reductionistic. Yet, reductionism is at the philosophical heart of the molecular biology revolution. Holistic science, the opposite of reductionistic science, has also acquired a bad name, perhaps due to an unfortunate association of the word “holistic” with new age pseudoscience. However, fortunately there is an increasingly popular euphemism that lacks the pejorative connotations of holism for scientists—“systems biology.” Since its debut a decade ago (23, 29), “systems biology” has appeared as a medical subject heading (MeSH) in PubMed more than 3,000 times. A fundamental tenet of systems biology is that cellular and organismal constituents are interconnected, so that their structure and dynamics must be examined in intact cells and organisms rather than as isolated parts. We recall that the late author Douglas Adams created a fictional detective named Dirk Gently who described his methods as “holistic” because he relied on the “fundamental interconnectedness of all things” to solve crimes (1). Gently used this to justify a large expense account, arguing that each of his personal expenses, like a beach holiday in the Bahamas, must be related to an ongoing investigation at some level. Although funding agencies are not likely to accept holistic accounting practices, holistic approaches have become increasingly popular in microbiology, sometimes advocated as superior to reductionistic ones (42). Researchers often adopt holistic or reductionistic approaches to study a problem without justifying their choice or explaining the advantages and limitations of such an approach. In this essay, we consider the dichotomy between holistic and reductionistic approaches to science and their implications for microbiology. First, however, a few definitions are in order.

Previous SectionNext Section

Types of reductionism.

“Reductionism” can have epistemological, ontological, and methodological meanings (34). Epistemological reductionism addresses the relationship between one scientific discipline and another and is defined as “the idea that the knowledge about one scientific domain can be reduced to another body of scientific knowledge” (7). For instance, can one, as Crick proposed, “explain all biology in terms of physics and chemistry” (12)? Certainly different scientific disciplines are interrelated and share fundamental principles, but discrete disciplines continue to exist because phenomena are best understood at one level or another. In fact, it can be argued that in practice disciplines such as physics and biology are epistemologically discontinuous, for science currently lacks a grand theory that allows us to connect such disparate phenomena as quantum mechanical states and the songs of birds. Epidemiology may be related to molecular biology, which in turn is related to chemistry and ultimately to physics, but the investigation of an ongoing cholera epidemic cannot be effectively carried out at the level of a molecule of cholera toxin or the quantum state of an electron around a single carbon atom within the toxin B subunit. In fact, the revolution in modern physics that replaced such bedrock assumptions of classical physics as continuity, separability, and determinism with discontinuity, entanglement, and the uncertainty principle has raised serious doubts about whether epistemological reduction can ever be realized. Exploring the epistemic relationships between different disciplines might be grist in the mill for a philosopher of science but does not seem a particularly fruitful endeavor for a working scientist.

Ontological reductionism presents an even thornier issue. Ontological reductionism is defined as “the idea that each particular biological system is constituted by nothing but molecules and their interactions” (7), in other words, the centuries-old debate about whether physical matter is the only reality in nature. Instances in which esoteric mathematical knowledge has later been found to be perfectly suited for describing newly discovered physical phenomena have prompted contemplation of the “unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics” in describing the physical world and raised deep philosophical questions about the possibility of a Platonic reality beyond our measurements and senses (44). Now, though, we find ourselves squarely within the realm of philosophy and feeling increasingly uncomfortable as we tiptoe gingerly through metaphysics.

The third category, methodological reductionism, describes the idea that complex systems or phenomena can be understood by the analysis of their simpler components. Methodological reduction is often traced back to Bacon, who in the early 17th century proposed that principles derived from specific cases might be applied to make general predictions (5, 21). Descartes soon afterward suggested that one should “divide each difficulty into as many parts as is feasible and necessary to resolve it” (16). As a contemporary example, a reductionistic approach would be to use a reporter fusion to the ctxA cholera toxin gene in order to identify environmental conditions responsible for regulating toxin production during infection (17). The experimenter would argue that regulation is most likely to occur at the level of transcription and that a simplified in vitro reporter system reduces the number of complicating experimental variables and facilitates analysis. An advocate of a more holistic approach could posit that cholera toxin gene expression is better studied during infection of a host and in the context of a genetic network of coregulated loci monitored over time (26, 32). In this example, reductionistic and holistic methodologies can be viewed as alternative approaches to understanding a complex system, with each providing useful, but limited, information. This essay focuses on the issue of methodological reductionism and leaves epistemological and ontological reductionism to the philosophers.

Previous SectionNext Section

Molecular biology: a triumph of reductionism.

If reductionistic methodology sounds familiar, that is because reductionism is implicit in much of molecular and cellular biology. Reductionism allows a microbiologist to explain that a bacterium fails to respond to therapy because it has acquired a gene encoding a beta-lactamase or that a patient exhibits enhanced susceptibility to infection because he has a mutant receptor for gamma interferon. Reductionism permits a microbiologist to screen Salmonella mutants for the ability to survive in cultured macrophages, knowing that this phenotype is predictive of the ability to cause mammalian infection (18). The successes of the reductionistic approach in biology during the latter half of the 20th century are undeniable, and yet limitations to methodological reductionism have been recognized. There are numerous examples of in vitro experimental observations made with isolated components of cells that are not directly applicable to the physiology of whole organisms. For example, mice deficient in Toll-like receptor 4 signaling are highly resistant to the effects of purified lipopolysaccharide but extremely susceptible to challenge with live bacteria (37, 48). The Infection and Immunity (IAI) Instructions to Authors state that “papers that utilize conserved microbial constituents (e.g., lipopolysaccharide, peptidoglycan) to stimulate immune responses, unless accompanied by experiments demonstrating relevance to the interaction between intact microbes and hosts or host cells,” are not within the scope of the journal. This is a tacit recognition of differences between pathogenic microbes and their parts and of the journal's preference for understanding the biology of whole organisms.

Previous SectionNext Section

Emergence of systems biology.

The last decade has witnessed a backlash against the reductionism of molecular biology. The philosophical antecedents of holism can be traced back to Aristotle, who is said to have pithily observed that “the whole is more than the sum of its parts.” Smuts later coined the term “holism” as “a tendency in nature to form wholes that are greater than the sum of the parts through creative evolution” (46). Systems biology has increasingly been touted as a revolutionary alternative to molecular biology and a means to transcend its inherent reductionism (2, 22, 29). Theoretical biologists, like Stuart Kauffman, have emphasized the ability of complex systems to give rise to emergent novel properties that are not predictable from the examination of individual components (6, 28). A humbling example is provided by the inability of detailed knowledge about the molecular structure of water to predict surface tension, a macroscopic phenomenon reflecting emergent behavior among water molecules. The issue of emergence imposes a theoretical limit on the knowledge available from reductionistic methodology. Systems biology has already had a transformative effect on microbiology. An emphasis on pathways, networks, and systems has given rise to powerful new bioinformatics and experimental methods. Genomic, microarray, and proteomic analyses are now commonplace in IAI (25, 35, 40). Systems approaches can be “top-down,” starting from “-omics” data and seeking to derive underlying explanatory principles, or “bottom-up,” starting with molecular properties and deriving models that can subsequently be tested and validated (8). The first approach begins with data collection and a description of phenomena, while the latter is more mechanism based, but both produce models of system behavior in response to perturbation that can be tested experimentally. The construction of synthetic regulatory circuits, the modeling of complex genetic and metabolic networks, and the measurement of transcriptional dynamics in single cells are just some of the new ways of analyzing complex phenomena that have invigorated microbiology (3, 11, 38, 39, 43). Systems biology approaches are particularly attractive for analyzing the exceedingly complex events that occur as a host encounters a pathogenic microbe or a vaccine (19, 26, 41).

Some limitations of reductionism may reflect current technological capabilities rather than inherent shortcomings of the approach. An early triumph for reductionism was the discovery that one could separate tobacco mosaic virus (TMV) into its RNA and coat protein components, which could then self-assemble when combined (30). However, in contrast to TMV, the self-assembly of more-complex structures is often impossible. This underscores the relationship between the inherent complexity of a system under study and the limits of methodological reductionism. However, the recent report that a complete functional genome can be inserted into bacterial protoplasm through advances in synthetic biology (20) demonstrates that technological advancements can greatly empower and validate reductionistic approaches. The limitations of reductionism are a moving boundary.

Previous SectionNext Section

A false dichotomy.

Methodological reductionism and holism are not truly opposed to each other (15). Each approach has its limitations. Reductionism may prevent scientists from recognizing important relationships between components or organisms in their natural settings, appreciating the evolutionary origins of processes and organisms, grasping probabilistic relationships underlying complicated and seemingly chaotic events, or perceiving heterogeneity and emergent multilevel properties of complex systems. Holism, on the other hand, is inherently more challenging due to the complexity of living organisms in their environment. Fundamental principles may be difficult to discern within complex systems due to confounding factors like redundancy and pleiotropy. Signal may be swamped by noise. The technology is seductive, but more data do not necessarily translate into more understanding. It is not yet certain whether current approaches to holism, such as systems biology, are adequate to cope with the challenges posed by emergent properties of complex biological systems. When fecklessly performed, systems biology may merely describe phenomena without providing explanation or mechanistic insight (9) or create virtual models that lack biological relevance.

It is difficult to imagine how a number of important scientific discoveries could have been made by any method other than a reductionistic approach. Without isolating DNA from other cellular constituents, Avery, Macleod, and McCarty could not have conclusively demonstrated that it alone was responsible for the transformation of the pneumococcus (4). Similarly, the power of reductionism was shown when a single Yersinia gene could confer upon Escherichia coli K-12 the ability to invade eukaryotic cells in tissue culture (24) or when the replacement of murine E-cadherin with its human counterpart rendered transgenic mice susceptible to oral challenge with Listeria (31). Likewise, there have been important observations for which a holistic approach has been essential. The discoveries that high levels of expression are the predominant barrier to horizontal gene transfer (47) and that Helicobacter pylori contains an unexpectedly large number of small untranslated RNAs and transcriptional start sites within operons (45) are but two recent examples. Confidence in these findings is critically dependent upon the authors' ability to use holistic high-throughput methods to generate and analyze enormous datasets: the attempted subcloning of nearly 250,000 genes and the sequencing of hundreds of thousands of cDNAs.

It should be emphasized that a combination of reductionistic and holistic approaches can be synergistic. In one example from the pathogenesis field, a holistic cRNA microarray analysis revealed that the RegIIIγ gene, encoding a C-type lectin, was strongly induced within intestinal Paneth cells following microbial colonization of germfree mice (10). The same lab subsequently went on to hypothesize that the RegIII lectin kills Gram-positive bacteria and demonstrated that it is able to bind the bacterial peptidoglycan carbohydrate backbone via a conserved (EPN) molecular motif, confirmed by site-specific mutagenesis of a single amino acid in the tripeptide (33). In another example, a holistic genome-wide RNA interference (RNAi) screen was first used to identify host factors important for influenza virus replication (27). When the screen suggested that viral replication was dependent on the cell cycle regulator p27, the investigators moved to a reductionistic approach and were able to demonstrate reduced influenza virus replication in a p27-deficient mouse in vivo.

Reductionism and holism are in fact interdependent and complementary. Reductionism is most useful if observations made in a simplified system allow accurate predictions, or at least the generation of hypotheses, to be made when returning to the complex natural world. However, interpreting observations from holistic studies may require mechanistic insights gained from earlier reductionistic work or may generate hypotheses that are amenable to testing through reductionistic experimental approaches. Ironically, Kitano noted that systems biology became possible only once advances in molecular biology allowed the emergence of genomic analysis and high-throughput measurements (29). We conclude that one approach is not necessarily better than another. Observations made in test tubes that have no correlates in the real world may not be very useful biology, but the mere creation of large datasets without interpretation, or holistic cartoon models that fail to achieve concordance with empirical reality, is also of little value.

Previous SectionNext Section

The way forward.

How can these alternative ways of doing science be reconciled? Investigators employing a reductionistic approach should attempt to test the predictive power of their observations in a more complex setting. For example, a biochemical study of protein-protein interactions should obtain evidence that such interactions and their consequences occur in an intact cell. An in vitro study of microbial resistance to a stress condition could be enhanced by experiments to determine whether the mechanism applies to interactions with host cells in which the particular stress occurs. A study showing the behavior of a microbe infecting host cells in tissue culture might be fruitfully expanded to include a bona fide infection of an animal host. Similarly, investigators should attempt to determine the degree to which reductionist findings are generalizable to other systems. An immunological study that shows the importance of a certain response in mice should be tested in other animal models or, where possible, in humans to ascertain whether general conclusions can be drawn. System-wide models, whether describing interactions of genes, proteins, small molecules, or organisms, should be rigorously tested and refined against real-life observations. Attempts should be made to identify the general organizing principles that underlie complex phenomena (36), and areas of discordance between predicted and observed results must be forthrightly addressed.

The recent focus on systems biology in microbiology is not a revolution or even a true paradigm shift, in the sense that reductionistic and holistic methodological approaches have been coexisting and thriving for centuries. One can argue that Darwin's theory of evolution represents an early example in which many reductionist observations on finches and domesticated pigeons were synthesized into a system that unified all of biology. The real seismic event in the recent rise of system biology arguably has more to do with the introduction of computer technology that allowed inexpensive calculation and the storage of prodigious amounts of information than with new conceptual approaches. Nevertheless, there is no denying the revolutionary impact of holistic thinking on the field, both in calling attention to situations in which reductionistic approaches have been deficient and in the generation of new experimental approaches for the analysis of complex systems. Computer technology has permitted the development of sophisticated mathematical, engineering, and computational tools that have allowed new questions to be asked. The central dogma of molecular biology (DNA → mRNA → protein) may not have been overturned, but it certainly has been extended (DNA → mRNA → protein → protein interactions → pathways → networks → cells → tissues → organisms → populations → ecologies) (23).

Whether one's methodology is primarily reductionistic or holistic, it is wise to begin by considering the limitations of the approach. This will help to limit imprudent extrapolation and point the way for further experimentation. In the end, the test of both reductionistic and holistic paradigms is their ability to explain and make useful predictions about the real world. No one said it would be easy. As Douglas Adams said, “If you try and take a cat apart to see how it works, the first thing you have on your hands is a non-working cat. Life is a level of complexity that almost lies outside our vision” (13).

Previous SectionNext Section

FOOTNOTES

    • Accepted manuscript posted online 14 February 2011.
  • The views expressed in this Editorial do not necessarily reflect the views of the journal or of ASM.

REFERENCES

  1. 1.↵

    Adams, D.1987. Dirk Gently's holistic detective agency. Simon and Schuster, New York, NY.

  2. 2.↵

    Aggarwal, K., and K. H. Lee.2003. Functional genomics and proteomics as a foundation for systems biology. Brief. Funct. Genomic. Proteomic.2:175-184.

  3. 3.↵

    Atkinson, M. R., M. A. Savageau, J. T. Myers, and A. J. Ninfa.2003. Development of genetic circuitry exhibiting toggle switch or oscillatory behavior in Escherichia coli. Cell113:597-607.

  4. 4.↵

    Avery, O. T., C. M. Macleod, and M. McCarty.1944. Studies on the chemical nature of the substance inducing transformation of pneumococcal types: induction of transformation by a desoxyribonucleic acid fraction isolated from pneumococcus type III. J. Exp. Med.79:137-158.

  5. 5.↵

    Bacon, F.1620. Novum organum. John Bill, London, United Kingdom.

  6. 6.↵

    Beresford, M. J.2010. Medical reductionism: lessons from the great philosophers. QJM103:721-724.

  7. 7.↵
  8. 8.↵

    Bruggeman, F. J., and H. V. Westerhoff.2007. The nature of systems biology. Trends Microbiol.15:45-50.

  9. 9.↵

    Casadevall, A., and F. C. Fang.2008. Descriptive science. Infect. Immun.76:3835-3836.

  10. 10.↵

    Cash, H. L., C. V. Whitham, C. L. Behrendt, and L. V. Hooper.2006. Symbiotic bacteria direct expression of an intestinal bactericidal lectin. Science313:1126-1130.

  11. 11.↵

    Covert, M. W., E. M. Knight, J. L. Reed, M. J. Herrgard, and B. O. Palsson.2004. Integrating high-throughput and computational data elucidates bacterial networks. Nature429:92-96.

  12. 12.↵

    Crick, F.1966. Of molecules and man. University of Washington Press, Seattle, WA.

  13. 13.↵
  14. 14.↵

    Dawkins, R.1996. The blind watchmaker. W.W. Norton, New York, NY.

  15. 15.↵

    De Backer, P., D. De Waele, and L. Van Speybroeck.2010. Ins and outs of systems biology vis-a-vis molecular biology: continuation or clear cut? Acta Biotheor.58:15-49.

  16. 16.↵

    Descartes, R.1637. Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison, et chercher la vérité dans les sciences. I. Maire, Leiden, Netherlands.

  17. 17.↵

    DiRita, V. J., and J. J. Mekalanos.1991. Periplasmic interaction between two membrane regulatory proteins, ToxR and ToxS, results in signal transduction and transcriptional activation. Cell64:29-37.

  18. 18.↵

    Fields, P. I., R. V. Swanson, C. G. Haidaris, and F. Heffron.1986. Mutants of Salmonella typhimurium that cannot survive within the macrophage are avirulent. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A.83:5189-5193.

  19. 19.↵

    Fruh, K., B. Finlay, and G. McFadden.2010. On the road to systems biology of host-pathogen interactions. Future Microbiol.5:131-133.

  20. 20.↵

    Gibson, D. G., J. I. Glass, C. Lartigue, et al.2010. Creation of a bacterial cell controlled by a chemically synthesized genome. Science329:52-56.

  21. 21.↵

    Glass, D. J., and N. Hall.2008. A brief history of the hypothesis. Cell134:378-381.

  22. 22.↵

    Hood, L., J. R. Heath, M. E. Phelps, and B. Lin.2004. Systems biology and new technologies enable predictive and preventative medicine. Science306:640-643.

  23. 23.↵

    Ideker, T., T. Galitski, and L. Hood.2001. A new approach to decoding life: systems biology. Annu. Rev. Genomics Hum. Genet.2:343-372.

  24. 24.↵

    Isberg, R. R., and S. Falkow.1985. A single genetic locus encoded by Yersinia pseudotuberculosis permits invasion of cultured animal cells by Escherichia coli K-12. Nature317:262-264.

  25. 25.↵

    Jeffrey, B. M., R. J. Suchland, K. L. Quinn, et al.2010. Genome sequencing of recent clinical Chlamydia trachomatis strains identifies loci associated with tissue tropism and regions of apparent recombination. Infect. Immun.78:2544-2553.

  26. 26.↵

    Kanjilal, S., R. Citorik, R. C. LaRocque, M. F. Ramoni, and S. B. Calderwood.2010. A systems biology approach to modeling Vibrio cholerae gene expression under virulence-inducing conditions. J. Bacteriol.192:4300-4310.

  27. 27.↵

    Karlas, A., N. Machuy, Y. Shin, et al.2010. Genome-wide RNAi screen identifies human host factors crucial for influenza virus replication. Nature463:818-822.

  28. 28.↵

    Kauffman, S.1993. The origins of order: self organization and selection in evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford, United Kingdom.

  29. 29.↵

    Kitano, H.2002. Systems biology: a brief overview. Science295:1662-1664.

  30. 30.↵

    Kushner, D. J.1969. Self-assembly of biological structures. Bacteriol. Rev.33:302-345.

  31. 31.↵

    Lecuit, M., S. Vandormael-Pournin, J. Lefort, et al.2001. A transgenic model for listeriosis: role of internalin in crossing the intestinal barrier. Science292:1722-1725.

  32. 32.↵

    Lee, S. H., D. L. Hava, M. K. Waldor, and A. Camilli.1999. Regulation and temporal expression patterns of Vibrio cholerae virulence genes during infection. Cell99:625-634.

  33. 33.↵

    Lehotzky, R. E., C. L. Partch, S. Mukherjee, et al.2010. Molecular basis for peptidoglycan recognition by a bactericidal lectin. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A.107:7722-7727.

  34. 34.↵

    Mazzocchi, F.2008. Complexity in biology. Exceeding the limits of reductionism and determinism using complexity theory. EMBO Rep.9:10-14.

  35. 35.↵

    McGill, M. A., D. G. Edmondson, J. A. Carroll, et al.2010. Characterization and serologic analysis of the Treponema pallidum proteome. Infect. Immun.78:2631-2643.

  36. 36.↵

    Mesarovic, M. D., S. N. Sreenath, and J. D. Keene.2004. Search for organising principles: understanding in systems biology. Syst. Biol. (Stevenage)1:19-27.

  37. 37.↵

    O'Brien, A. D., D. L. Rosenstreich, I. Scher, et al.1980. Genetic control of susceptibility to Salmonella typhimurium in mice: role of the LPS gene. J. Immunol.124:20-24.

  38. 38.↵

    Ozbudak, E. M., M. Thattai, H. N. Lim, B. I. Shraiman, and A. Van Oudenaarden.2004. Multistability in the lactose utilization network of Escherichia coli. Nature427:737-740.

  39. 39.↵

    Park, H., W. Pontius, C. C. Guet, et al.2010. Interdependence of behavioural variability and response to small stimuli in bacteria. Nature468:819-823.

  40. 40.↵

    Pearson, M. M., D. A. Rasko, S. N. Smith, and H. L. Mobley.2010. Transcriptome of swarming Proteus mirabilis. Infect. Immun.78:2834-2845.

  41. 41.↵

    Querec, T. D., R. S. Akondy, E. K. Lee, et al.2009. Systems biology approach predicts immunogenicity of the yellow fever vaccine in humans. Nat. Immunol.10:116-125.

  42. 42.↵

    Raoult, D.2010. Technology-driven research will dominate hypothesis-driven research: the future of microbiology. Future Microbiol.5:135-137.

  43. 43.↵

    Rosenfeld, N., J. W. Young, U. Alon, P. S. Swain, and M. B. Elowitz.2005. Gene regulation at the single-cell level. Science307:1962-1965.

  44. 44.↵

    Sarukkai, S.2005. Revisiting the ‘unreasonable effectiveness’ of mathematics. Curr. Sci.88:415-423.

  45. 45.↵

    Sharma, C. M., S. Hoffmann, F. Darfeuille, et al.2010. The primary transcriptome of the major human pathogen Helicobacter pylori. Nature464:250-255.

  46. 46.↵

    Smuts, J. C.1926. Holism and evolution. Macmillan, London, United Kingdom.

  47. 47.↵

    Sorek, R., Y. Zhu, C. J. Creevey, et al.2007. Genome-wide experimental determination of barriers to horizontal gene transfer. Science318:1449-1452.

  48. 48.↵

    Vazquez-Torres, A., B. A. Vallance, M. A. Bergman, et al.2004. Toll-like receptor 4 dependence of innate and adaptive immunity to Salmonella: importance of the Kupffer cell network. J. Immunol.172:6202-6208.

  • Copyright © 2011, American Society for Microbiology

Reductionism can be defined as the breaking down of a complex phenomenon into simpler components. Reductionist explanations can be desirable by scientists of all areas because they offer a simpler explanation for a complex phenomenon. This process can be useful because the effects of one variable can be isolated.

A prime example of a reductionist explanation for abnormal behaviour is brain damage. This sort of physiological reductionism reduces behaviour to the action, or malfunction of neurotransmitters and hormones located in the brain. Physiological reductionism has been considered to adopt a more humane approach to the treatment of mental illness, as it doesn’t inherently blame the patient, as the illness is beyond their control. However, to just reduce brain damage to the release of neurotransmitters in the brain is surely an inadequate explanation as it ignores environmental and cultural factors. Genetics is another physiological explanation, the idea that we inherit certain genes which promote certain undesirable or abnormal behaviour; that are once again out of our control. This is a solely reductionist-oriented explanation and once again fails to take into account any subsequent environmental or cultural factors.

There are many arguments against reductionism in psychology. One of the most predominant arguments is the involvement of environmental factors in shaping our behaviour. A person’s environment can shape their behaviour through to old age, and whilst an individual may be born with certain genes, environmental factors such as society and a person’s family can shape any further behaviour. Also, experimental research does not always equate to real life and may dangerously misrepresent it. Dividing a system into parts assumes that if you put them back together, you will restore the original system. This may be true for simple systems but not for complex ones. Knowledge of the individual parts may not give you an understanding of how the whole thing operates or of its function.

Pro-reductionistic arguments lean towards atomic theory. Since all animals are made of atoms, our behaviour must be explainable at this level, i.e. can be reduced to a physical level. This leads to two main assumptions. First, behaviour is nothing more than the sum of its parts. Second, there is no special “life force” added to the mix, no mental events are independent of physical events and every physical event has a physical cause. This argument dismisses the relevance of the mind and the role it plays in the development of emotional, cultural and individualistic factors.

Atinkson and Shiffrin’s (1968) multi-store model of memory was a reductionist and linear account of how memory works. This could be classified as “machine reductionism”, as the brain is likened to a computer. Humanistic psychologists believe that the individual reacts as an organized whole rather than a set of stimulus-response links. This argument is governed under the concept of Holism. This approach focuses on systems as a whole rather than focusing on the constituent parts and suggests that we cannot predict how the whole system will behave from a knowledge of its components. Reductionist explanations can therefore play only a limited role in understanding behaviour. However, reducing behaviour to a form that can be studied is productive. This is indeed useful when trying to understand how things work.

In reducing a concept to its component parts and simplest terms many aspects of it are disregarded. Reductionism does not give a full explanation for an otherwise complicated subject such as evolution or memory. Evolutionary psychologists explain behaviour in terms of natural selection and sexual selection. Such explanations are reductionist because they suggest that all behaviour can be reduced to genetic influences and the principle of adaptive ness. In terms of evolution the reductionist view ignores environmental factors and the huge part they play in a species evolution. By reducing it to its component parts the complicated matter of evolution can never fully be explained, thus leading to a simple but incomplete explanation.

Individual factors are hard to explain under reductionism, because reductionist explanations generalise behaviour; despite being in its simplest terms. Each individual being is unique and responds differently when compared to another person. A reductionist explanation would be genetics, but the same behaviour in two people could be caused by separate environmental and biological factors, thus limiting the reductionist explanation.

The concept of emotion is inherently ignored by the reductionist explanation, mainly because it is improbable that a persons emotions can be explained through neurotransmitters. However, certain hormones are released when a person feels elated, excited or scared such as adrenaline and certain endorphins. This draws to the conclusion that perhaps there is a link between behaviour (namely emotions) and the biological release of neurotransmitters. Reductionism has been criticised as being an inaccurate explanation of reality, it only uncovers the component parts, which leads to an incomplete construction of reality. Reality is probably best understood by acknowledging all aspects of explanations, both physiological and environmental or emotional.

A fundamental problem with reductionism is that is lures psychologists into making impractical cause and effect links. This means that various “emergent” properties in our society such as history and economy can be overlooked, resulting in reduced accounts of human behaviour. A further argument against reductionism is that reductionist goals are inappropriate for psychology. Humanistic psychologists believe that it does not make sense to study reductionist accounts of human behaviour. Another hindrance of reductionism is the somewhat “erroneous” explanations of behaviour. Methodological reductionism aims to make the study of behaviour more accessible by reducing variables. The findings of such experimental research will inevitably have low generalizibility and cannot be applied to other settings. This is because the key variables have been simplified. For example, memory research often involves learning nonsense syllables or word lists, a simplification of real world memory tasks. However the findings are mistakenly generalized to memory in general. If memory is studied in the real world, findings may be different.

Reductionist explanations can be useful, by reducing complicated concepts to their component parts behaviour can be more easily understood. However, sometimes this offers too much of a simple solution to an otherwise more complicated problem. For example giving anti-depressants to someone who is depressed may seem like an optimal solution, but this may overlook the real problem; such as family problems. This is one fundamental problem that the reductionist explanation has; many compound things such as family and genetics usually surround behaviour. Also, there are emergent properties in society, which the reductionist explanation disregards. The extent to which the reason for behaviour can be reduced depends on the type of behaviour. Each society brings different morals, cultural diversity and environments, so perhaps a more broadened perspective on the matter would be most productive to science; and psychologists.

Other Useful Articles

  • reductionist explanations in psychology

Comments

  • Written by eddybiel
  • Suitable for Psychology A-level
  • Suitable for PYA4 or PYA5

Article by TSR User on Thursday 15 February 2018

0 comments

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *